Book
7
SOCRATES’
NARRATION CONTINUES:
SOCRATES: Next, then, compare the
effect of education and that of the lack of it on our nature to an experience
like this. Imagine human beings living in an underground, cavelike dwelling,
with an entrance a long way up that is open to the light and as wide as the
cave itself. They have been there since childhood, with their necks and legs
fettered, so that they are fixed in the same place, able to see only in front
of them, because their fetter prevents them from turning their heads around.
Light is provided by a fire burning far above and behind them. Between the
prisoners and the fire, there is an elevated road stretching. Imagine that
along this road a low wall has been built—like the screen in front of people
that is provided by puppeteers, and above which they show their puppets.
GLAUCON: I am imagining it.
SOCRATES: Also imagine, then, that
there are people alongside the wall carrying multifarious artifacts that
project above it—statues of people and other animals, made of stone, wood,
and every material. And as you would expect, some of the carriers are talking
and some are silent.
GLAUCON: It is a strange image you are describing, and strange
prisoners.
SOCRATES: They are like us. I mean, in
the first place, do you think these prisoners have ever seen anything of
themselves and one another besides the shadows that the fire casts on the
wall of the cave in front of them?
GLAUCON: How could they, if they have to keep their heads motionless throughout
life?
SOCRATES: What about the things carried
along the wall? Isn’t the same true where they are concerned?
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: And if they could engage in
discussion with one another, don’t you think they would assume that the words
they used applied to the things they see passing in front of them?
GLAUCON: They would have to.
SOCRATES: What if their prison also had
an echo from the wall facing them? When one of the carriers passing along the
wall spoke, do you think they would believe that anything other than the
shadow passing in front of them was speaking?
GLAUCON: I do not, by Zeus.
SOCRATES: All in all, then, what the
prisoners would take for true reality is nothing other than the shadows of
those artifacts.
GLAUCON: That’s entirely inevitable.
SOCRATES: Consider, then, what being
released from their bonds and cured of their foolishness would naturally be
like, if something like this should happen to them. When one was freed and
suddenly compelled to stand up, turn his neck around, walk, and look up
toward the light, he would be pained by doing all these things and be unable
to see the things whose shadows he had seen before, because of the flashing
lights. What do you think he would say if we told him that what he had seen
before was silly nonsense, but that now—because he is a bit closer to what
is, and is turned toward things that are more—he sees more correctly? And in particular, if we
pointed to each of the things passing by and compelled him to answer what
each of them is, don’t you think he would be puzzled and believe that the
things he saw earlier were more truly real than the ones he was being shown?
GLAUCON: Much more so.
SOCRATES: And if he were compelled to
look at the light itself, wouldn’t his eyes be pained and wouldn’t he turn
around and flee toward the things he is able to see, and believe that they
are really clearer than the ones he is being shown?
GLAUCON: He would.
SOCRATES: And if someone dragged him by
force away from there, along the rough, steep, upward path, and did not let
him go until he had dragged him into the light of the sun, wouldn’t he be
pained and angry at being treated that way? And when he came into the light,
wouldn’t he have his eyes filled with sunlight and be unable to see a single
one of the things now said to be truly real?
GLAUCON: No, he would not be able to—at least not right away.
SOCRATES: He would need time to get
adjusted, I suppose, if he is going to see the things in the world above. At
first, he would see shadows most easily, then images of men and other things
in water, then the things themselves. From these, it would be easier for him
to go on to look at the things in the sky and the sky itself at night, gazing
at the light of the stars and the moon, than during the day, gazing at the
sun and the light of the sun.
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: Finally, I suppose, he would
be able to see the sun—not reflections of it in water or some alien place,
but the sun just by itself in its own place—and be able to look at it and see
what it is like.
GLAUCON: He would have to.
SOCRATES: After that, he would already
be able to conclude about it that it provides the seasons and the years,
governs everything in the visible world, and is in some way the cause of all
the things that he and his fellows used to see.
GLAUCON: That would clearly be his next step.
SOCRATES: What about when he reminds
himself of his first dwelling place, what passed for wisdom there, and his
fellow prisoners? Don’t you think he would count himself happy for the change
and pity the others?
GLAUCON: Certainly.
SOCRATES: And if there had been honors,
praises, or prizes among them
for the one who was sharpest at identifying the shadows as they passed
by;
and was best able to remember which usually came earlier, which later,
and
which simultaneously; and who was thus best able to prophesize the
future,
do you think that our man would desire these rewards or envy those
among
the prisoners who were honored and held power? Or do you think he
would feel with Homer that he would much prefer to “work the earth as
a
serf for another man, a man without possessions of his own,”1 and go
through any sufferings, rather than share their beliefs and live as
they do?
GLAUCON: Yes, I think he would rather suffer anything than live like
that.
SOCRATES: Consider this too, then. If
this man went back down into the
cave and sat down in his same seat, wouldn’t his eyes be filled with
darkness, coming suddenly out of the sun like that?
GLAUCON: Certainly.
SOCRATES: Now, if he had to compete
once again with the perpetual prisoners in recognizing the shadows, while his
sight was still dim and before
his eyes had recovered, and if the time required for readjustment was
not
short, wouldn’t he provoke ridicule? Wouldn’t it be said of him that
he had
returned from his upward journey with his eyes ruined, and that it is
not
worthwhile even to try to travel upward? And as for anyone who tried
to
free the prisoners and lead them upward, if they could somehow get
their
hands on him, wouldn’t they kill him?
GLAUCON: They certainly would.
SOCRATES: This image, my dear Glaucon,
must be fitted together as a
whole with what we said before. The realm revealed through sight
should
be likened to the prison dwelling, and the light of the fire inside it
to the
sun’s power. And if you think of the upward journey and the seeing of
things above as the upward journey of the soul to the intelligible
realm, you
won’t mistake my intention—since it is what you wanted to hear about.
Only the god knows whether it is true. But this is how these phenomena
seem to me: in the knowable realm, the last thing to be seen is the
form of
the good, and it is seen only with toil and trouble. Once one has seen
it,
however, one must infer that it is the cause of all that is correct
and beautiful in anything, that in the visible realm it produces both light
and its
source, and that in the intelligible realm it controls and provides
truth and
understanding; and that anyone who is to act sensibly in private or
public
must see it.
GLAUCON: I agree, so far as I am able.
SOCRATES: Come on, then, and join me in
this further thought: you
should not be surprised that the ones who get to this point are not
willing to
occupy themselves with human affairs, but that, on the contrary, their
souls
are always eager to spend their time above. I mean, that is surely
what we
would expect, if indeed the image I described before is also accurate
here.
GLAUCON: It is what we would expect.
SOCRATES: What about when someone,
coming from looking at divine
things, looks to the evils of human life? Do you think it is
surprising that he
behaves awkwardly and appears completely ridiculous, if—while his
sight is
still dim and he has not yet become accustomed to the darkness around
him—he is compelled, either in the courts or elsewhere, to compete
about
the shadows of justice, or about the statues of which they are the
shadows;
and to dispute the way these things are understood by people who have
never seen justice itself?
GLAUCON: It is not surprising at all.
SOCRATES: On the contrary, anyone with
any sense, at any rate, would
remember that eyes may be confused in two ways and from two causes:
when they change from the light into the darkness, or from the
darkness
into the light. If he kept in mind that the same applies to the soul,
then
when he saw a soul disturbed and unable to see something, he would not
laugh absurdly. Instead, he would see whether it had come from a
brighter
life and was dimmed through not having yet become accustomed to the
dark, or from greater ignorance into greater light and was dazzled by
the
increased brilliance. Then he would consider the first soul happy in
its
experience and life, and pity the latter. But even if he wanted to
ridicule it,
at least his ridiculing it would make him less ridiculous than
ridiculing a
soul that had come from the light above.
GLAUCON: That’s an entirely reasonable claim.
SOCRATES: Then here is how we must
think about these matters, if that is
true: education is not what some people boastfully declare it to be.
They
presumably say they can put knowledge into souls that lack it, as if
they
could put sight into blind eyes.
GLAUCON: Yes, they do say that.
SOCRATES: But here is what our present
account shows about this power to
learn that is present in everyone’s soul, and the instrument with
which each
of us learns: just as an eye cannot be turned around from darkness to
light
except by turning the whole body, so this instrument must be turned
around from what-comes-to-be together with the whole soul, until it is
able
to bear to look at what is and at the brightest thing that is—the one
we call
the good. Isn’t that right?
GLAUCON: Yes.
SOCRATES: Of this very thing, then,
there would be a craft—namely, of this
turning around—concerned with how this instrument can be most easily
and effectively turned around, not of putting sight into it. On the
contrary,
it takes for granted that sight is there, though not turned in the
right way or
looking where it should look, and contrives to redirect it
appropriately.
GLAUCON: That’s probably right.
SOCRATES: Then the other so-called
virtues of the soul do seem to be
closely akin to those of the body: they really are not present in it
initially,
but are added later by habit and practice. The virtue of wisdom, on
the
other hand, belongs above all, so it seems, to something more divine,
which never loses its power, but is either useful and beneficial or
useless and
harmful, depending on the way it is turned. Or haven’t you ever
noticed in
people who are said to be bad, but clever, how keen the vision of
their little
soul is and how sharply it distinguishes the things it is turned
toward? This
shows that its sight is not inferior, but is forced to serve vice, so
that the
sharper it sees, the more evils it accomplishes.
GLAUCON: I certainly have.
SOCRATES: However, if this element of
this sort of nature had been hammered at right from childhood, and struck
free of the leaden weights, as it
were, of kinship with becoming, which have been fastened to it by
eating
and other such pleasures and indulgences, which pull its soul’s vision
downward2—if, I say, it got rid of these and turned toward truly real things,
then
the same element of the same people would see them most sharply, just
as it
now does the things it is now turned toward.
GLAUCON: That’s probably right.
SOCRATES: Isn’t it also probable,
then—indeed, doesn’t it follow necessarily from what was said before—that
uneducated people who have no experience of true reality will never
adequately govern a city, and neither will
people who have been allowed to spend their whole lives in education.
The
former fail because they do not have a single goal in life at which
all their
actions, public and private, inevitably aim; the latter because they
would
refuse to act, thinking they had emigrated, while still alive, to the
Isles of
the Blessed.
GLAUCON: True.
SOCRATES: It is our task as founders,
then, to compel the best natures to
learn what was said before3 to be the most important thing: namely, to
see
the good; to ascend that ascent. And when they have ascended and
looked
sufficiently, we must not allow them to do what they are allowed to do
now.
GLAUCON: What’s that, then?
SOCRATES: To stay there and refuse to
go down again to the prisoners in
the cave and share their labors and honors, whether the inferior ones
or the
more excellent ones.
GLAUCON: You mean we are to treat them unjustly, making them live a
worse life when they could live a better one?
SOCRATES: You have forgotten again, my
friend, that the law is not concerned with making any one class in the city
do outstandingly well, but is
contriving to produce this condition in the city as a whole,
harmonizing
the citizens together through persuasion or compulsion, and making
them
share with each other the benefit they can confer on the community.4
It
produces such men in the city, not in order to allow them to turn in
whatever direction each one wants, but to make use of them to bind the city
together.
GLAUCON: That’s true. Yes, I had forgotten.
SOCRATES: Observe, then, Glaucon, that
we won’t be unjustly treating
those who have become philosophers in our city, but that what we will
say
to them, when we compel them to take care of the others and guard
them,
will be just. We will say:“When people like you come to be in other
cities,
they are justified in not sharing in the others’ labors. After all,
they have
grown there spontaneously, against the will of the constitution in
each of
them. And when something grows of its own accord and owes no debt for
its upbringing, it has justice on its side when it is not keen to pay
anyone
for its upbringing. But both for your own sakes and for that of the
rest of
the city, we have bred you to be leaders and kings in the hive, so to
speak.
You are better and more completely educated than the others, and
better
able to share in both types of life.5 So each of you in turn must go
down to
live in the common dwelling place of the other citizens and grow
accustomed to seeing in the dark. For when you are used to it, you will see
infinitely better than the people there and know precisely what each image
is,
and also what it is an image of, because you have seen the truth about
fine,
just, and good things. So the city will be awake, governed by us and
by you;
not dreaming like the majority of cities nowadays, governed by men who
fight against one another over shadows and form factions in order to
rule—
as if that were a great good.6 No, the truth of the matter is surely
this: a city
in which those who are going to rule are least eager to rule is
necessarily
best and freest from faction, whereas a city with the opposite kind of
rulers
is governed in the opposite way.”
GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.
SOCRATES: Then do you think the people
we have nurtured will disobey
us when they hear these things, and be unwilling to share the labors
of the
city, each in turn, and wish instead to live the greater part of their
time
with one another in the pure realm?
GLAUCON: No, they couldn’t possibly. After all, we will be giving just
orders to just people. However, each of them will certainly go to rule
as to
something necessary, which is exactly the opposite of what is done by
those
who now rule in each city.
SOCRATES: That’s right, comrade. If you
can find a way of life that is better than ruling for those who are going to
rule, your well-governed city
will become a possibility. You see, in it alone the truly rich will
rule—those
who are rich not in gold, but in the wealth the happy must have:
namely, a
good and rational life. But if beggars—people hungry for private goods
of
their own—go into public life, thinking that the good is there for the
seizing, then such a city is impossible. For when ruling is something fought
over, such civil and domestic war destroys these men and the rest of
the city
as well.
GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.
SOCRATES: Do you know of any other sort
of life that looks down on
political offices besides that of true philosophy?
GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I do not.
SOCRATES: But surely it is those who
are not lovers of ruling who must go
do it. Otherwise, the rivaling lovers will fight over it.
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: Who else, then, will you
compel to go be guardians of the city
if not those who know best what results in good government, and have
different honors and a better life than the political?
GLAUCON: No one else.
SOCRATES: Do you want us to consider
now how such people will come
to exist, and how we will lead them up to the light, like those who
are said
to have gone up from Hades to the gods?
GLAUCON: Yes, of course that’s what I want.
SOCRATES: It seems, then, that this is
not a matter of flipping a potsherd,7
but of turning a soul from a day that is a kind of night in comparison
to the
true day—that ascent to what is, which we say is true philosophy.
GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.
SOCRATES: Then mustn’t we try to
discover what subjects have the power
to bring this about?
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: So what subject is it,
Glaucon, that draws the soul from what
is coming to be to what is? It occurs to me as I am speaking that we
said,
didn’t we, that these people must be athletes of war when they are
young?8
GLAUCON: Yes, we did say that.
SOCRATES: Then the subject we are
looking for must also have this characteristic in addition to the former one.
GLAUCON: Which?
SOCRATES: It must not be useless to
warlike men.
GLAUCON: If possible, it must not.
SOCRATES: Now, earlier they were
educated by us in musical and physical
training.
GLAUCON: They were.
SOCRATES: And surely physical training
is concerned with what-comesto-be and dies, since it oversees the growth and
decay of the body.
GLAUCON: Obviously.
SOCRATES: So it could not be the
subject we are looking for.
GLAUCON: No, it could not.
SOCRATES: Is it, then, the musical
training we described before?
GLAUCON: But it is just the counterpart of physical training, if you
remember. It educated the guardians through habits, conveying by
harmony a certain harmoniousness of temper, not knowledge; and by rhythm
a certain rhythmical quality. Its stories, whether fictional or nearer
the
truth, cultivated other habits akin to these. But as for a subject
that leads to
the destination you have in mind, of the sort you are looking for now,
there
was nothing of that in it.
SOCRATES: Your reminder is exactly to
the point. It really does not have
anything of that sort. You’re a marvelous fellow, Glaucon, but what is
there
that does? The crafts all seemed to be somehow menial.9
GLAUCON: Of course. And yet, what subject is left that is separate
from
musical and physical training, and from the crafts?
SOCRATES: Well, if we have nothing left
beyond these, let’s consider one
of those that touches all of them.
GLAUCON: Which?
SOCRATES: Why, for example, that common
thing, the one that every
type of craft, thought, and knowledge uses, and that is among the
first
things everyone has to learn.
GLAUCON: Which one is that?
SOCRATES: That inconsequential matter
of distinguishing the numbers
one, two, and three. In short, I mean number and calculation. Or isn’t
it
true that every type of craft and knowledge must share in them?
GLAUCON: Indeed it is.
SOCRATES: Then warfare must too.
GLAUCON: It must.
SOCRATES: In tragedies, at any rate,
Palamedes is always showing up
Agamemnon as a totally ridiculous general. Haven’t you noticed? He
says
that by inventing numbers he established how many troops there were in
the army at Ilium and counted their ships and everything else. The
implication is that they had not been counted before, and that Agamemnon
apparently did not even know how many feet he had, since he did not know
how to count. What kind of general do you think that made him?
GLAUCON: A very strange one, I’d say, if there is any truth in that.
SOCRATES: Won’t we posit this subject,
then, as one a warrior has to learn
so he can count and calculate?
GLAUCON: It is more essential than anything else—if, that is, he is
going
to know anything at all about marshaling his troops—or if he is even
going
to be human, for that matter.
SOCRATES: Then do you notice the same
thing about this subject as I do?
GLAUCON: What?
SOCRATES: That in all likelihood it is
one of the subjects we were looking
for that naturally stimulate the understanding. But no one uses it
correctly,
as something that really is fitted in every way to draw us toward
being.
GLAUCON: How do you mean?
SOCRATES: I will try to make what I
believe clear, at any rate. I will distinguish for myself the things that lead
in the direction we mentioned from
those that do not. Then you must look at them along with me, and
either
agree or disagree, so that we may see more clearly whether the
distinction is
as I imagine.
GLAUCON: Show me the things you mean.
SOCRATES: All right, I will show you,
if you can see that some senseperceptions do not summon the understanding to
look into them, because
the judgment of sense-perception is itself adequate; whereas others
encourage it in every way to look into them, because sense-perception does
not
produce a sound result.
GLAUCON: You are obviously referring to things appearing in the
distance
and illusionist paintings.
SOCRATES: No, you are not quite getting
what I mean.
GLAUCON: Then what do you mean?
SOCRATES: The ones that do not summon
the understanding are all those
that do not at the same time result in an opposite sense-perception.
But the
ones that do I call summoners. That is when sense-perception does not make
one thing any more clear than its opposite, regardless of whether what
strikes the senses is close by or far away. What I mean will be
clearer if you
look at it this way: these, we say, are three fingers—the smallest,
the second,
and the middle finger.
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: Assume that I am talking
about them as being seen from close
by. Now consider this about them with me.
GLAUCON: What?
SOCRATES: It is obvious, surely, that
each of them is equally a finger, and it
makes no difference whether it is seen to be in the middle or at
either end;
whether it is dark or pale, thick or thin, or anything else of that
sort. You
see, in all these cases, the soul of most people is not compelled to
ask the
understanding what a finger is, since sight does not at any point
suggest to
it that a finger is at the same time the opposite of a finger.
GLAUCON: No, it does not.
SOCRATES: It is likely, then, that a
perception of that sort would not summon or awaken the understanding.
GLAUCON: It is likely.
SOCRATES: Now, what about their bigness
and smallness? Does sight perceive them adequately? Does it make no
difference to it whether one of
them is in the middle or at the end? And is it the same with the sense
of
touch, as regards thickness and thinness, hardness and softness? What
about
the other senses, then—do they make such things sufficiently clear? Or
doesn’t each of them work as follows: in the first place, the sense
that deals
with hardness must also deal with softness; and it reports to the soul
that it
perceives the same thing to be both hard and soft?
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: In cases of this sort then,
isn’t the soul inevitably puzzled as to
what this sense-perception means by hardness, if it says that the same
thing
is also soft; and in the case of the sense-perception of lightness and
heaviness, what it means lightness and heaviness are, if what is heavy is
light or
what is light heavy?
GLAUCON: Yes, indeed, those are strange messages for the soul to
receive
and do need to be examined.
SOCRATES: It is likely, then, that it
is in cases of this sort that the soul,
summoning calculation and understanding, first tries to determine
whether
each of the things reported to it is one or two.
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: If there are obviously two,
won’t each of them be obviously
one and distinct?
GLAUCON: Yes.
SOCRATES: If each of them is one, then,
and both together are two, the
soul will understand that the two are separate. I mean, it would not
understand inseparable things as two, but as one.
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: But sight, we say, saw
bigness and smallness, not as separate,
but as mixed up together. Right?
SOCRATES: Then they obviously lead toward truth.
GLAUCON: To an unnatural degree.
SOCRATES: Then they would belong, it seems, among
the subjects we are
seeking. I mean, a soldier must learn them in order to marshal his troops;
and a philosopher, because it is necessary to be rising up out of becoming
so as to grasp being, or he will never become able to calculate.
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: And our guardian is, in fact, both a
warrior and a philosopher.
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: Then it would be appropriate, Glaucon,
to prescribe this subject in our legislation and to persuade those who are
going to take part in
what is most important in the city to go in for calculation and take it up,
not as laymen do, but staying with it until they reach the point at which
they see the nature of the numbers by means of understanding itself; not
like tradesmen and retailers, caring about it for the sake of buying and
selling, but for the sake of war and for ease in turning the soul itself
around
from becoming to truth and being.
GLAUCON: Very well put.
SOCRATES: Moreover, it occurs to me now that the
subject of calculation
has been mentioned, how refined it is and in how many ways it is useful for
our purposes, provided you practice it for the sake of knowledge rather
than trade.
GLAUCON: Which ways?
SOCRATES: Why, in the very one we were talking
about just now. It gives
the soul a strong lead upward and compels it to discuss the numbers
themselves, never permitting anyone to propose for discussion numbers
attached
to visible or tangible bodies. I mean, you surely know what people who are
clever in these matters are like. If, in the course of the argument, someone
tries to divide the number one itself, they laugh and won’t permit it. If you
divide
it, they multiply it, taking care that the number one never appears to
be, not one, but many parts.
GLAUCON: That’s very true.
SOCRATES: Then what do you think would happen,
Glaucon, if someone
were to ask them:“What kind of numbers are you amazing fellows discussing,
where the number one is as you assume it to be, wholly equal in each
and every case, without the least difference, and having no internal parts?”
What do you think they would answer?
GLAUCON: I think they would answer that they are talking about those
that are accessible only to thought and can be grasped in no other way.
SOCRATES: Do you see then, my friend, that this
subject really does seem
to be necessary to us, since it apparently compels the soul to use understanding
itself on the truth itself?
GLAUCON: It does so very strongly, in fact.
SOCRATES: Now, have you ever noticed that those
who are naturally good
at calculation are also naturally quick in all subjects, so to speak, and
that
those who are slow, if they are educated and exercised in it, even if they
are
benefited in no other way, nonetheless improve and become generally
sharper than they were?
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: Moreover, I do not think you will easily
find many subjects
that are harder to learn or practice than it.
GLAUCON: No indeed.
SOCRATES: For all these reasons, then, this
subject is not to be neglected.
On the contrary, the very best natures must be educated in it.
GLAUCON: I agree.
SOCRATES: Well, then, let’s require that one.
Second, let’s consider
whether the subject that follows after it is also appropriate for our
purposes.
GLAUCON: Which one? Or do you mean geometry?
SOCRATES: That’s it exactly.
GLAUCON: Insofar as it pertains to war, it is clearly appropriate. You see,
when it comes to setting up camp, occupying a region, gathering and
ordering troops, and all the other maneuvers armies make whether in battle
itself or on the march, it makes all the difference whether someone is
skilled in geometry or not.
SOCRATES: But still, for things like that, even a
little bit of geometry—and
of calculation—would suffice. What we need to consider is whether the
greater and more advanced part of it tends to make it easier to see the form
of the good. And that tendency, we say, is to be found in anything that
compels the soul to turn itself around toward the region in which lies the
happiest of the things that are; the one the soul must do everything possible
to see.
GLAUCON: You are right.
SOCRATES: Therefore, if geometry compels one to
look at being, it is
appropriate; but if at becoming, it is inappropriate.
GLAUCON: Yes, that’s what we are saying.
SOCRATES: Now, no one with even a little
experience of geometry will
dispute with us that this science is itself entirely the opposite of what is
said
about it in the accounts of its practitioners.
GLAUCON: How so?
SOCRATES: Well, they say completely ridiculous
things about it because
they are so hard up. I mean, they talk as if they were practical people who
make all their arguments for the sake of action. They talk of squaring,
applying, adding, and the like; whereas, in fact, the entire subject is
practiced for the sake of acquiring knowledge.
GLAUCON: Absolutely.
SOCRATES: Mustn’t we also agree on a further
point?
GLAUCON: What?
SOCRATES: That it is knowledge of what always is,
not of something that
comes to be and passes away.
GLAUCON: That’s easy to agree to, since geometry is knowledge of what
always is.
SOCRATES: In that case, my noble fellow, it can
draw the soul toward truth
and produce philosophical thought by directing upward what we now
wrongly direct downward.
GLAUCON: More than anything else.
SOCRATES: More than anything else, then, we must
require the inhabitants of your beautiful city not to neglect geometry in any
way, since even
its byproducts are not insignificant.
GLAUCON: What are they?
SOCRATES: The ones you mentioned that are
concerned with war. And in
addition, when it comes to being better able to pick up any subject, we
surely know there is a world of difference between someone with a grasp of
geometry and someone without one.
GLAUCON: Yes, by Zeus, a world of difference.
SOCRATES: Shall we prescribe it, then, as a second
subject for the young?
GLAUCON: Let’s.
SOCRATES: What about astronomy? Shall we make it
the third? What do
you think?
GLAUCON: That’s fine with me, at least. I mean, a better awareness of the
seasons, months, and years is no less appropriate for a general than for a
farmer or navigator.
SOCRATES: You are funny! You are like someone who
is afraid that the
masses will think he is prescribing useless subjects. It is no
inconsequential
task—indeed it is a very difficult one—to become persuaded that in everyone’s
soul there is an instrument that is purified and rekindled by such subjects
when it has been blinded and destroyed by other pursuits—an
instrument that it is more important to preserve than 10,000 eyes, since
only with it can the truth be seen. Those who share your belief that this is
so will think you are speaking incredibly well, while those who are completely
unaware of it will probably think you are talking nonsense, since
they can see no other benefit worth mentioning in these subjects. So,
decide right now which group you are engaging in discussion. Or is it neither
of them, and are you making your arguments mostly for your own
sake—though you do not begrudge anyone else whatever profit he can get
from them?
GLAUCON: That’s what I prefer—to speak, question, and answer mostly
for my own sake.
SOCRATES: Let’s backtrack a bit. You see, we were
wrong just now about
the subject that comes after geometry.
GLAUCON: How so?
SOCRATES: After a plain surface, we went
immediately to a solid that was
revolving, without taking one just by itself. But the right way is to take up
the third dimension after the second. And it, I suppose, consists of cubes
and of whatever shares in depth.
GLAUCON: Yes, you are right. But Socrates, that subject has not even been
investigated yet.
SOCRATES: There are two reasons for that. Because
no city values it, it is
not vigorously investigated, due to its difficulty. And investigators need a
director if they are to discover anything. Now, in the first place, such a
director is difficult to find. Second, even if he could be found, as things
stand now, those who investigate it are too arrogant to obey him. But if an
entire city served as his co-director and took the lead in valuing this
subject, then they would obey him, and consistent and vigorous investigation
would reveal the facts about it. For even now, when it is not valued by the
masses and is hampered by investigators who lack any account of its
usefulness—all the same, in spite of all these handicaps, the force of its
appeal has
caused it to be developed. So it would not be at all surprising if the facts
about it were revealed in any case.
GLAUCON: Yes, indeed, it is an outstandingly appealing subject. But
explain more clearly to me what you were saying just now. You took geometry,
presumably, as dealing with plane surface.
SOCRATES: Yes.
GLAUCON: Then at first you put astronomy after it, but later you went
back on that.
SOCRATES: Yes, the more I hurried to get through
them all, the slower I
went! You see, the subject dealing with the dimension of depth was next.
But because of the ridiculous state the investigation of it is in, I passed
it by
and spoke of astronomy—which deals with the motion of things having
depth—after geometry.
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: Let’s then prescribe astronomy as the
fourth subject, on the
assumption that solid geometry, which we are now omitting, will be available
if a city takes it up.
GLAUCON: That seems reasonable. And since you reproached me just now,
Socrates, for praising astronomy in a vulgar manner, I will now praise it
your way. You see, I think it is clear to everyone that it compels the soul to
look upward and leads it from things here to things there.
SOCRATES: It is clear to everyone except me, then,
since that is not how I
think of it.
GLAUCON: Then how do you think of it?
SOCRATES: As it is handled today by those who
teach philosophy, it makes
the soul look very much downward.
GLAUCON: How do you mean?
SOCRATES: In my opinion, your conception of
“higher studies” is a good
deal too generous! I mean, if someone were looking at something by leaning
his head back and studying ornaments on a ceiling, it seems as though
you would say that he is looking at them with his understanding, not with
his eyes! Maybe you are right and I am foolish. You see, I just cannot
conceive of any subject making the soul look upward except the one that is
concerned with what is—and that is invisible. If anyone tries to
learn something about perceptible things, whether by gaping upward or
squinting
downward, I would say that he never really learns—since there is no knowledge
to be had of such things—and that his soul is not looking up but
down, whether he does his learning lying on his back on land or on sea!
GLAUCON: A fair judgment! You are right to reproach me. But what did
you mean, then, when you said that astronomy must be learned in a different
way than people learn it at present, if it is going to be useful with regard
to what we are talking about?
SOCRATES: It is like this: these ornaments in the
heavens, since they are
ornaments in something visible, may certainly be regarded as having the
most beautiful and most exact motions that such things can have. But these
fall far short of the true ones—those motions in which the things that are
really fast or really slow, as measured in true numbers and as forming all
the
true geometrical figures, are moved relative to one another, and that move
the things that are in them. And these, of course, must be grasped by reason
and thought, not by sight. Don’t you agree?
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: Therefore, we should use the ornaments
in the heavens as models to help us study these other things.10 It is just as
if someone chanced to
find diagrams by Daedalus or some other craftsman or painter, which were
very carefully drawn and worked out. I mean, anyone experienced in geometry
who saw such things would consider them to be very beautifully executed, I
suppose. But he would think it ridiculous to examine them seriously
in order to find there the truth about equals, doubles, or any other ratio.
GLAUCON: How could it be anything but ridiculous?
SOCRATES: Don’t you think, then, that a real
astronomer will feel the
same way when he looks at the motions of the stars? He will believe that
the craftsman of the heavens arranged them and all that is in them in the
most beautiful way possible for such things. But as for the ratio of night to
day, of these to a month, of a month to a year, or of the motions of the
stars
to them or to each other, don’t you think he will consider it strange to
believe that they are always the same and never deviate in the least, since
they are connected to body and are visible things, or to seek by every
means possible to grasp the truth about them?
GLAUCON: That’s what I think—anyway, now that I hear it from you!
SOCRATES: Just as in geometry, then, it is by
making use of problems that
we will pursue astronomy too. We will leave the things in the heavens
alone, if we are really going to participate in astronomy and make the
naturally wise element in the soul useful instead of useless.
GLAUCON: The task you are prescribing is a lot bigger than anything now
attempted in astronomy.
SOCRATES: And I suppose we will prescribe other
subjects in the same
way, if we are to be of any benefit as lawgivers. But can you in fact suggest
any other appropriate subjects?
GLAUCON: Not at the moment, anyway.
SOCRATES: But motion, it seems to me, presents
itself, not just in one
form, but in several. A wise person could probably list them all, but there
are two that are evident even to us.
GLAUCON: What are they?
SOCRATES: Besides the one we have discussed, there
is also its counterpart.
GLAUCON: What’s that?
SOCRATES: It is probable that as the eyes fasten
on astronomical motions,
so the ears fasten on harmonic ones, and that these two sciences are somehow
akin, as the Pythagoreans say. And we agree, Glaucon. Don’t we?
GLAUCON: We do.
SOCRATES: Then, since the task is so huge,
shouldn’t we ask them their
opinion and whether they have anything to add, all the while guarding our
own requirement?
GLAUCON: What’s that?
SOCRATES: That those we will be rearing should
never attempt to learn
anything incomplete,11 anything that does not always come out at the place
all things should reach—the one we mentioned just now in the case of
astronomy.12 Or don’t you know that people do something similar with
harmony, too? They measure audible concordances and sounds against one
another, and so labor in vain, just like astronomers.
GLAUCON: Yes, by the gods, and pretty ridiculous they are, too. They talk
about something they call a “dense interval” or quarter tone13—putting
their ears to their instruments, like someone trying to overhear what the
neighbors are saying. And some say they hear a tone in between, and that it
is the
shortest interval by which they must measure, while others argue that
this tone sounds the same as a quarter tone. Both groups put ears before the
understanding.
SOCRATES: You mean those excellent fellows who vex
their strings, torturing them and stretching them on pegs. I won’t draw out
the analogy by
speaking of blows with the pick, or the charges laid against strings that are
too responsive or too unresponsive. Instead, I will drop the analogy and say
that I do not mean these people, but the ones we just said we were going to
question about harmonics. You see, they do the same as the astronomers do.
I mean, it is in these audible concordances that they search for numbers,
but they do not ascend to problems or investigate which numbers are in
concord and which are not, or what the explanation is in each case.
GLAUCON: But that would be a daimonic task!
SOCRATES: Yet, it is useful in the search for the
beautiful and the good!
Pursued for any other purpose, though, it is useless.
GLAUCON: I suppose so.
SOCRATES: Moreover, I take it that if the
investigation of all the subjects
we have mentioned arrives at what they share in common with one
another and what their affinities are, and draws conclusions about their
kinship, it does contribute something to our goal and is not labor in vain;
but
that otherwise it is in vain.
GLAUCON: I have the same hunch myself. But you are still talking about a
very big task, Socrates.
SOCRATES: Do you mean the prelude, or what? Or
don’t you know that
all these subjects are merely preludes to the theme14 itself that must be
learned? I mean, you surely do not think that people who are clever in
these matters are dialecticians.
GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I do not. Although, I have met a few exceptions.
SOCRATES: But did it ever seem to you that those
who can neither give an
account nor approve one know what any of the things are that we say they
must know?
GLAUCON: Again, the answer is no.
SOCRATES: Then isn’t this at last, Glaucon, the
theme itself that dialectical
discussion sings? It itself is intelligible. But the power of sight imitates
it. We
said that sight tries at last to look at the animals themselves, the stars
themselves, and, in the end, at the sun itself.15 In the same way, whenever
someone tries, by means of dialectical discussion and without the aid of any
sense-perceptions, to arrive through reason at the being of each thing
itself,
and does not give up until he grasps what good itself is16 with understanding
itself, he reaches the end of the intelligible realm, just as the other
reached the end of the visible one.
GLAUCON: Absolutely.
SOCRATES: Well, then, don’t you call this
journey17 dialectic?
GLAUCON: I do.
SOCRATES: Then the release from bonds and the
turning around from
shadows to statues and the light; and then the ascent out of the cave to the
sun; and there the continuing inability to look directly at the animals, the
plants, and the light of the sun, but instead at divine reflections in water
and
shadows of the things that are, and not, as before, merely at shadows of
statues thrown by another source of light that, when judged in relation to
the
sun, is as shadowy as they—all this practice of the crafts we mentioned has
the power to lead the best part of the soul upward until it sees the best
among the things that are, just as before the clearest thing in the body was
led to the brightest thing in the bodily and visible world.
GLAUCON: I accept that this is so. And yet, I think it is very difficult to
accept; although—in another way—difficult not to accept! All the same,
since the present occasion is not our only opportunity to hear these things,
but we will get to return to them often in the future, let’s assume that what
you said about them just now is true and turn to the theme itself, and
discuss it in the same way as we did the prelude. So, tell us then, in what
way
the power of dialectical discussion works, into what kinds it is divided, and
what roads it follows. I mean, it is these, it seems, that would lead us at
last
to that place which is a rest from the road, so to speak, for the one who
reaches it, and an end of his journey.
SOCRATES: You won’t be able to follow me any
farther, my dear Glaucon—though not because of any lack of eagerness on my
part. You would
no longer see an image of what we are describing, but the truth itself as it
seems to me, at least.18 Whether it is really so or not—that’s not something
on which it is any longer worth insisting. But that there is some such thing
to be seen, that is something on which we must insist. Isn’t that so?
GLAUCON: Of course.
SOCRATES: And mustn’t we also insist that the
power of dialectical discussion could reveal it only to someone experienced
in the subjects we
described, and cannot do so in any other way?
GLAUCON: Yes, that is worth insisting on, too.
SOCRATES: At the very least, no one will dispute
our claim by arguing that
there is another road of inquiry that tries to acquire a systematic and
wholly
general grasp of what each thing itself is. By contrast, all the other crafts
are
concerned with human beliefs and appetites, with growing or construction,
or with the care of growing or constructed things. As for the rest, we
described them as to some extent grasping what is—I mean, geometry and
the subjects that follow it. For we saw that while they do dream about what
is, they cannot see it while wide awake as long as they make use of
hypotheses that they leave undisturbed, and for which they cannot give any
argument. After all, when the first principle is unknown, and the conclusion
and the steps in between are put together out of what is unknown, what
mechanism could possibly turn any agreement reached in such cases into
knowledge?19
GLAUCON: None.
SOCRATES: Therefore, dialectic is the only
investigation that, doing away
with hypotheses, journeys to the first principle itself in order to be made
secure. And when the eye of the soul is really buried in a sort of barbaric
bog, dialectic gently pulls it out and leads it upward, using the crafts we
described to help it and cooperate with it in turning the soul around. From
force of habit, we have often called these branches of knowledge. But they
need another name, since they are clearer than belief and darker than
knowledge. We distinguished them by the term “thought” somewhere
before.21 But I don’t suppose we will dispute about names, with matters as
important as those before us to investigate.
GLAUCON: Of course not, just as long as they express the state of clarity
the soul possesses.
SOCRATES: It will be satisfactory, then, to do
what we did before and call
the first section knowledge, the second thought, the third opinion, and the
fourth imagination. The last two together we call belief, the other two,
understanding.22 Belief is concerned with becoming; understanding with
being. And as being is to becoming, so understanding is to belief; and as
understanding is to belief, so knowledge is to belief and thought to
imagination. But as for the ratios between the things these deal with, and
the
division of either the believable or the intelligible section into two, let’s
pass
them by, Glaucon, in case they involve us in discussions many times longer
than the ones we have already gone through.
GLAUCON: I agree with you about the rest of them, anyway, insofar as I
am able to follow.
SOCRATES: So don’t you, too, call someone a
dialectician when he is able
to grasp an account of the being of each thing? And when he cannot do so,
won’t you, too, say that to the extent that he cannot give an account of
something either to himself or to another, to that extent he does not
understand it?
GLAUCON: How could I not?
SOCRATES: Then the same applies to the good.
Unless someone can give
an account of the form of the good, distinguishing it from everything else,
and can survive all examination as if in a battle, striving to examine23
things
not in accordance with belief, but in accordance with being; and can journey
through all that with his account still intact, you will say that he does
not know the good itself or any other good whatsoever. And if he does
manage to grasp some image of it, you will say that it is through belief, not
knowledge, that he grasps it; that he is dreaming and asleep throughout his
present life; and that, before he wakes up here, he will arrive in Hades and
go to sleep forever.
GLAUCON: Yes, by Zeus, I will certainly say all that.
SOCRATES: Then as for those children of yours, the
ones you are rearing
and educating in your discussion, if you ever reared them in fact, I don’t
suppose that, while they are still as irrational as the proverbial lines,24
you
would allow them to rule in your city or control the most important things.
GLAUCON: No, of course not.
SOCRATES: Won’t you prescribe in your legislation,
then, that they are to
give the most attention to the education that will enable them to ask and
answer questions most knowledgeably?
GLAUCON: I will prescribe it—together with you.
SOCRATES: Doesn’t it seem to you, then, that
dialectic is just like a capstone we have placed on top of the subjects, and
that no other subject can
rightly be placed above it, but that our account of the subjects has now
come to an end?
GLAUCON: It does.
SOCRATES: Then it remains for you to deal with the
distribution of these
subjects: to whom we will assign them and in what way.
GLAUCON: Clearly.
SOCRATES: Do you remember what sort of people we
chose in our earlier
selection of rulers?25
GLAUCON: How could I not?
SOCRATES: Well then, as regards the other
requirements too, you must
suppose that these same natures are to be chosen, since we have to select
the most secure, the most courageous, and—as far as possible—the
bestlooking.26 In addition, we must look not only for people who have a noble
and valiant character, but for those who also have natural qualities
conducive to this education of ours.
GLAUCON: Which ones in particular?
SOCRATES: They must be keen on the subjects, bless
you, and learn them
without difficulty. For people’s souls are much more likely to give up during
strenuous studies than during physical training. The pain is more their
own, you see, since it is peculiar to them and not shared with the body.
GLAUCON: That’s true.
SOCRATES: We must also look for someone who has a
good memory, is
persistent, and is wholeheartedly in love with hard work. How else do you
suppose he would be willing to carry out such hard physical labors and also
complete so much learning and training?
GLAUCON: He would not, not unless his nature were an entirely good one.
SOCRATES: In any case, the mistake made at
present—which, as we said
before, explains why philosophy has fallen into dishonor—is that unworthy
people take it up. For illegitimate people should not have taken it up, but
genuine ones.
GLAUCON: How do you mean?
SOCRATES: In the first place, the one who takes it
up must not be halfhearted in his love of hard work, with one half of him
loving hard work
and the other shirking it. That is what happens when someone is a lover of
physical training and a lover of hunting and a lover of all kinds of hard
bodily labor; yet is not a lover of learning, a lover of listening, or a keen
investigator, but hates the work involved in all such things. And someone
whose love of hard work tends in the opposite direction is also defective.
GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.
SOCRATES: Similarly with regard to truth, won’t we
say that a soul is
maimed if it hates a voluntary lie, cannot endure to have one in itself, and
is
greatly angered when others lie; but is nonetheless content to accept an
involuntary lie, does not get irritated when it is caught being ignorant, and
bears its ignorance easily, wallowing in it like a pig?27
GLAUCON: Absolutely.
SOCRATES: And with regard to temperance, courage,
high-mindedness,
and all the other parts of virtue, too, we must be especially on our guard to
distinguish the illegitimate from the genuine. You see, when private
individuals or cities do not know how to investigate all these things fully,
they
unwittingly employ defectives and illegitimates as their friends or rulers
for
whatever services they happen to need.
GLAUCON: Yes, that’s just what happens.
SOCRATES: So we must take good care in all these
matters, since, if we
bring people who are sound of limb and mind to so important a subject,
and train and educate them in it, justice itself will not find fault with us,
and we will save both the city and its constitution. But if we bring people
of a different sort to it, we will achieve precisely the opposite and let
loose
an even greater flood of ridicule upon philosophy as well.
GLAUCON: That would be a shame.
SOCRATES: It certainly would. But I seem to have
made myself a little
ridiculous just now.
GLAUCON: In what way?
SOCRATES: I forgot we were playing and spoke too
vehemently. You see,
while I was speaking I looked upon philosophy, and when I saw it undeservedly
showered with abuse, I suppose I got irritated and, as if I were
angry with those responsible, I said what I had to say in too serious a
manner.
GLAUCON: Not too serious for me, by Zeus, as a member of the audience.
SOCRATES: But too serious for me as the speaker.
In any case, let’s not forget that in our earlier selection we chose older
people, but here that is not
permitted. You see, we must not believe Solon when he says that as someone
grows older, he is able to learn a lot. On the contrary, he is even less
able to learn than to run. It is to young people that all large and frequent
labors properly belong.
GLAUCON: Necessarily so.
SOCRATES: Well, then, calculation, geometry, and
all the preparatory education that serves as preparation for dialectic must
be offered to them in
childhood—and not in the shape of compulsory instruction, either.
GLAUCON: Why’s that?
SOCRATES: Because a free person should learn
nothing slavishly. For while
compulsory physical labors do no harm to the body, no compulsory
instruction remains in the soul.
GLAUCON: That’s true.
SOCRATES: Well, then, do not use compulsion, my
very good man, to
train the children in these subjects; use play instead. That way you will
also
be able to see better what each of them is naturally suited for.
GLAUCON: What you say makes sense.
SOCRATES: Don’t you remember that we also said
that the children were
to be led into war on horseback as observers, and that, wherever it is safe,
they should be brought to the front and given a taste of blood, just like
young dogs?
GLAUCON: I do remember.
SOCRATES: Those who always show the greatest
facility in dealing with all
these labors, studies, and fears must be enrolled in a unit.
GLAUCON: At what age?
SOCRATES: After they are released from compulsory
physical training. For
during that period, whether it is two or three years, they are incapable of
doing anything else, since weariness and sleep are enemies of learning. At
the same time, one of the important tests of each of them is how he fares in
physical training.
GLAUCON: It certainly is.
SOCRATES: Then, after that period, those selected
from among the
twenty-year-olds will receive greater honors than the others. Moreover, the
subjects they learned in no particular order in their education as children,
they must now bring together into a unified vision of their kinship with
one another and with the nature of what is.
GLAUCON: That, at any rate, is the only instruction that remains secure in
those who receive it.
SOCRATES: It is also the greatest test of which
nature is dialectical and
which is not. For the person who can achieve a unified vision is dialectical,
and the one who cannot isn’t.
GLAUCON: I agree.
SOCRATES: Well, then, you will have to look out
for those among them
who most possess that quality; who are resolute in their studies and also
resolute in war and the other things conventionally expected of them. And
when they have passed their thirtieth year, you will have to select them in
turn from among those selected earlier and assign them yet greater honors,
and test them by means of the power of dialectical discussion to see which
of them can relinquish his eyes and other senses, and travel on in the
company of truth to what itself is. And here, comrade, you have a task that
needs a lot of safeguarding.
GLAUCON: How so?
SOCRATES: Don’t you realize the harm caused by
dialectical discussion as
it is currently practiced?
GLAUCON: What harm?
SOCRATES: Its practitioners are filled with
lawlessness.
GLAUCON: They certainly are.
SOCRATES: Do you think it is at all surprising
that this happens to them?
Aren’t you sympathetic?
GLAUCON: Why should I be?
SOCRATES: It is like the case of a supposititious
child brought up amid
great wealth, a large and powerful family, and many flatterers, who finds
out, when he has become a man, that he is not the child of his professed
parents and that he cannot discover his real ones. Do you have any hunch as
to what his attitude would be to the flatterers, and to his supposed parents,
during the time when he did not know about the exchange, and, on the
other hand, when he did know? Or would you rather hear my hunch?
GLAUCON: I would.
SOCRATES: Well, then, my hunch is that he would be
more likely to
honor his father, his mother, and the rest of his supposed family than the
flatterers, less likely to overlook any of their needs, less likely to treat
them
lawlessly in word or deed, and less likely to disobey them than the
flatterers
in any matters of importance, in the time when he did not know the truth.
GLAUCON: Probably so.
SOCRATES: But when he became aware of the truth,
on the other hand,
my hunch is that he would withdraw his honor and devotion from his family and
increase them for the flatterers, whom he would obey far more than
before, and he would begin to live the way they did, spend time with them
openly, and—unless he was thoroughly good by nature—care nothing for
that father of his or any of the rest of his supposed family.
GLAUCON: All that would probably happen as you say. But how is it like
the case of those who take up argument?
SOCRATES: As follows. I take it we hold from
childhood convictions about
what things are just and fine; we are brought up with them as with our
parents; we obey and honor them.
GLAUCON: Yes, we do.
SOCRATES: And there are also other practices,
opposite to those, which
possess pleasures that flatter our soul and attract it to themselves, but
which
do not persuade people who are at all moderate—who continue to honor
and obey the convictions of their fathers.
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: What happens, then, when someone of that
sort is met by the
question,“What is the fine?” and, when he answers what he has heard from
the traditional lawgiver, the argument refutes him; and by refuting him
often and in many ways, reduces him to the belief that the fine is no more
fine than shameful, and the same with the just, the good, and the things he
honored most—what do you think he will do after that about honoring
and obeying his earlier convictions?
GLAUCON: It is inevitable that he won’t honor or obey them in the same
way.
SOCRATES: Then when he no longer regards them as
honorable or as his
own kin the way he did before, and cannot discover the true ones, will he
be likely to adopt any other sort of life than the one that flatters him?
GLAUCON: No, he won’t.
SOCRATES: And so he will be taken, I suppose, to
have changed from
being law-abiding to being lawless.
GLAUCON: Inevitably.
SOCRATES: Isn’t it likely, then, that this is what
will happen to people who
take up argument in that way, and, as I said just now, don’t they deserve a
lot of sympathy?
GLAUCON: Yes, and pity too.
SOCRATES: Then if you do not want your
thirty-year-olds to be objects of
such pity, won’t you have to employ every sort of precaution when they
take up argument?
GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.
SOCRATES: And isn’t one very effective precaution
not to let them taste
argument while they are young? I mean, I don’t suppose it has escaped your
notice that when young people get their first taste of argument, they misuse
it as if it were playing a game, always using it for disputation.28 They
imitate
those who have refuted them by refuting others themselves,29 and, like
puppies, enjoy dragging and tearing with argument anyone within reach.
GLAUCON: Excessively so.
SOCRATES: Then, when they have refuted many
themselves and been
refuted by many, they quickly fall into violently disbelieving everything
they believed before. And as a result of this, they themselves and the whole
of philosophy as well are discredited in the eyes of others.
GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.
SOCRATES: But an older person would not be willing
to take part in such
madness. He will imitate someone who is willing to engage in dialectical
discussion and look for the truth, rather than someone who plays at
disputation as a game. He will be more moderate himself and will bring honor,
rather than discredit, to the practice.
GLAUCON: That’s right.
SOCRATES: And wasn’t everything we said before
this also said as a precaution—that those with whom one takes part in
arguments are to be orderly and steady by nature, and not, as now, those,
however unsuitable, who chance to come along?
GLAUCON: Yes, it was.
SOCRATES: Is it enough, then, if
someone devotes himself continuously and strenuously to taking part in
argument, doing nothing else, but training in it just as he did in the
physical training that is its counterpart, but for twice as many years?
GLAUCON: Do you mean six years or four?
SOCRATES: It does not matter. Make it five. You
see, after that, you must make them go down into the cave again, and compel
them to take command in matters of war and the other offices suitable for
young people, so that they won’t be inferior to the others in experience. And
in these offices, too, they must be tested to see whether they will remain
steadfast when they are pulled in different directions, or give way.
GLAUCON: How much time do you assign to that?
SOCRATES: Fifteen years. Then, at the age of
fifty, those who have survived the tests and are entirely best in every
practical task and every science
must be led at last to the end and compelled to lift up the radiant light of their
souls, and to look toward what itself provides light for everything. And once
they have seen the good itself, they must use it as their model and put the
city, its citizens, and themselves in order throughout the remainder of their
lives, each in turn. They will spend most of their time doing philosophy, but,
when his turn comes, each must labor in politics and rule for the city’s
sake, not as something fine, but rather as something that must be done.30 In
that way, always having educated others like themselves to take their place
as guardians of the city, they will depart for the Isles of the Blessed and
dwell there. And the city will publicly establish memorials and sacrifices to
them as daimons,31 if the Pythia agrees; but if not, as happy and divine
people.
GLAUCON: Like a sculptor,32 Socrates, you have produced thoroughly beautiful
ruling men!
SOCRATES: And ruling women, too,
Glaucon. You see, you must not think that what I have said applies any more
to men than it does to those women of theirs who are born with the
appropriate natures.
GLAUCON: That’s right, if indeed they are to share everything equally with the
men, as we said.
SOCRATES: Well, then, do you agree that the things
we have said about the city and its constitution are not altogether wishful
thinking; that it is difficult for them to come about, but possible in a way,
and in no way except the one we described: namely, when one or more true
philosophers
|
No comments:
Post a Comment